FREEDOM OF SPEECH AS A PRODUCT OF DEMOCRACY, PART 1

Volume 27 1 Issue 3

1993

Arnold H. Loewy

FREEDOM OF SPEECH AS A PRODUCT OF DEMOCRACY*

Arnold H. Loewy**

There are very nearly as many (if not more) rationales for free­dom of speech as there are books and articles on the subject. With­out attempting to canvass them all, I think that they can be di­vided into two generic theories. One theory suggests that freedom of speech is essentially teleological or consequentialist, i.e. it exists to serve some other goal, usually effective participation in the dem­ocratic process.[1] [2] The other theory, which is deontological or nor­mative, suggests that freedom of speech exists as an end in itself rather than as a means towards accomplishing something else.[3] Of course, these theories are not necessarily mutually exclusive.[4]

Under a strict consequentialist viewpoint, all speech that is not directly related to the claimed desired consequence is unprotected. For example, if the desired consequence is thought to be the tem­perate rational discussion of political issues, any speech that is not temperate, rational, and political would be unprotected.[5] [6] Some of the more extreme deontological rationales, on the other hand, are attacked as being nothing more than a specific illustration of the generic concept of liberty.®

The theory advanced herein rejects the view that freedom of speech is simply another liberty. Like Professor Frederick Schauer, I agree that freedom of speech is special.[7] On the other hand, I do not believe that freedom of speech must contribute to other values, such as democracy, in order to be protected. Freedom of speech should be viewed as a product of democracy rather than as a ser­vant to it. The best analogy is to the franchise. We hope that per­mitting all manner of citizens to vote (the uncouth barbarian no less than the highly educated political scientist) will bring us a more perfect government; whether it does or does not, our sense of basic fairness demands that we all have the opportunity to partici­pate. By similar reasoning, freedom of speech cannot be subject to any kind of quality control analysis.

  1. Neutrality: The Distinctive Characteristic of Freedom of Speech

Before proceeding further, it is imperative that we understand the most important characteristic of freedom of speech, its abso­lute neutrality. Although sometimes described as a “liberal” doc­trine, it is not liberal in the political sense of the term. Conserva­tive speech is protected as thoroughly as liberal speech.

Two of the Supreme Court’s best-known freedom of speech quo­tations chart the boundaries of the freedom. In one, Justice Jack­son with characteristic eloquence announced for the Court: “If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion. . . .”[8] In the other, Justice Powell, for the Court, announced simply: “[T]here is no such thing as a false idea.”[9] Taken together, these statements stand for the proposition that, as a matter of law, at least in the realm of ideas or opinions, there can be no official truth or falsity. Every idea or opinion, no matter how wrong­headed, can compete in the marketplace.

In describing the government’s role in freedom of speech, I have employed the term “neutrality.” Neutrality is a benign-sounding term. Indeed, in another context, the Court has described it as “wholesome.”[10] But, “wholesome neutrality” is not the only term that could describe the government’s role. Other less benign terms such as “agnostic” or even “amoral” could describe the govern­ment’s role as well. And so, we must ask ourselves why we should have a constitutional provision that requires the government to act amorally.

  1. Skepticism or Tolerance

Much of the most recent freedom of speech literature has ques­tioned whether skepticism or tolerance best explains freedom of speech.[11] Most of those that have spoken of the dichotomy have opted for tolerance.[12] In their view, some ideas are unquestionably false, and we ought not pretend that they might be true. By being tolerant of these ideas, however, government teaches the value of tolerance, thereby imbuing its citizens with a sense of its importance.[13]

There are several things wrong with this analysis. First, many, if not most, ideas that need constitutional protection are not ideas that we should tolerate. At most, we should permit them to be said, but not tolerate their substance. More importantly, the edu­cative function is anathematic to the First Amendment. By al­lowing speech, the government does not say that the particular speech is good for us — only that it would be worse to allow gov­ernment to decide what is not good for us. As Justice Jackson put it:

[I]t cannot be the duty, because it is not the right, of the state to protect the public against false doctrine. The very purpose of the First Amendment is to foreclose public authority from assuming a guardianship of the public mind through regulating the press, speech, and religion. In this field every person must be his own watchman for truth, because the forefathers did not trust any gov­ernment to separate the true from the false for us. Nor would I.[14]

Does this mean that amorality, or moral relativism is basic con­stitutional dogma? I think not. We can know as citizens that much which is uttered or printed is at the least morally bankrupt. We do not, however, endorse those hateful words by permitting them to enter the marketplace. Put differently, the legal disability de­scribed by Justice Jackson does not mean that government cannot know falsity when it hears it; it simply means that the government is under a legal disability to do anything about it. Once we stop thinking about freedom of speech as an endorsement of the speaker, much of the argument for suppressing evil speech disap­pears. We can then understand the government’s duty towards such speech to be legal, not moral, skepticism.

I do not mean to suggest that tolerance is not part of the first amendment. Indeed, with disgusting regularity, we have to tolerate revolting ideas that we really wish would go away. However, toler­ance is not the reason for freedom of speech; it is merely a neces­sary by-product of that freedom, and an unfortunate one at that. The reason for freedom of speech is the absolute legal disability of government to distinguish that speech which is good for us from that speech which is not.

A perfect paradigm is the attempted Nazi march in Skokie, Illi­nois, a Chicago suburb inhabited by a large Jewish population, in­cluding a substantial number of Holocaust survivors.[15] [16] Dean Lee Bollinger, an advocate of the “tolerance” theory of the first amend­ment, contends that Skokie was a close case, but that even there principles of tolerance should uphold the Nazis’ right to speak.[17]1 disagree. If there were a principled line between tolerable and in­tolerable speech, the Nazis would surely be on the intolerable side of it. The reason that the Nazis were protected is that there is no such line. Because there is no such line, the Nazis could not have been close to it. Therefore, upholding their right to speak in Sko­kie should have been an easy, albeit painful, decision in much the same way that upholding the right to burn the flag was painful for Justice Kennedy.16

Why does the populace feel such a keen desire to do something to prevent Nazi speech or flag burning? I think that the answer lies in the counter-intuitive nature of freedom of speech.[18] We know that the speakers are wrong, and we cannot help equating permis­sion with endorsement. At least, we want to draw a line between ordinary hateful speech, and beyond-the-pale hateful speech. The problem is that no such line can be drawn. Unless all ideas are protected, no ideas are protected. This is not just a “slippery slope” argument.[19] I am not suggesting that Nazis should be pro­tected in Skokie because I am worried about the next case. The point is that a society that prevents its government from separating good and bad ideas for it cannot allow that government to sup­press bad ideas, even in cases like Skokie.

  • Marketplace of Ideas

Since Justice Holmes’ famous dissent in Abrams v. United States,[20] the Court has justified, the government’s disability to sup­press bad ideas on the “marketplace of ideas” theory.[21] Under this theory, all ideas have the right to be tested in the marketplace without being subjected to any government screening for plausibil­ity. In recent years, the marketplace theory has become a popular whipping-post among commentators. One line of attack is that, for a variety of reasons such as poverty and inarticulateness, all ideas do not have equal access to the marketplace.[22] This attack mis- perceives the government’s duty; its role is simply to refrain from interfering with the marketplace, not necessarily to facilitate it.[23] In the realm of free speech, laissez-faire is still acceptable policy, or at least more acceptable than actively interfering with some of the market participants.

Another attack on the “marketplace” theory is that while it seeks to separate truth from falsity, it denies that truth can be ascertained. If we cannot find the truth, why bother to keep look­ing for it?[24] This argument fails to separate philosophical truth or falsity from government-endorsed truth or falsity. Without a doubt, individuals can be satisfied to a moral certainty that some ideas are good (true) and others are bad (false). Indeed, virtually an entire society may, and should condemn as evil much that passes for free speech. But, it cannot be condemned as false, and hence beyond the pale, by the government. So viewed, the “mar­ketplace” theory is not internally inconsistent. It serves societal and individual efforts to ascertain truth, but from the perspective of government prohibition, the concept of truth or falsity is a legal impossibility.

Professor Alexander Bickel attacks the “marketplace” theory at a more fundamental level, arguing that not all ideas deserve to compete. After quoting Holmes’ famous observation, “[I]f in the long run the beliefs expressed in proletarian dictatorship are des­tined to be accepted by the dominant forces of the community, [the only] meaning of free speech is that they should be given their chance and have their way[,]”[25] [26] [27] Bickel observes: “If in the long run the belief, let us say, in genocide is destined to be accepted by the dominant forces of the community, the only meaning of free speech is that it should be given its chance and have its way. Do we believe that? Do we accept it?”2B Bickel certainly does not.

To illustrate his point, Bickel related this story:

[A] crowd gathered in front of the ROTC building at a university some years ago. At this university, as elsewhere, some members of the faculty and administration had undertaken to discharge the function of cardinal legate to the barbarians, going without the walls every so often to negotiate the sack of the city. On this occasion, with the best of intentions, members of the faculty joined the crowd and participated in the discussion of whether or not to set fire to the building. The faculty, I gather took the negative, and I assume that none of the students in the affirmative could have been guilty of inciting the crowd. The matter was ultimately voted upon, and the affirmative lost — narrowly. But the negative taken by the faculty was only one side of a debate which the faculty rendered legitimate by engaging in it.28

From this, Bickel concludes: “Where nothing is unspeakable, noth­ing is undoable.”[28]

The error of Bickel’s analysis, of course, is his equation of per­mission and endorsement. To illustrate the magnitude of his error, let us posit a university of which Bickel were the autocratic presi­dent. I assume that at such a university, it would be impermissible to debate the burning of buildings. Who would take that limitation seriously? The “barbarians?” The faculty? I assume that the barbarians would continue to debate burning the building (or al-

ternatively they might just burn it). The faculty, on the other hand, would take the debate limitation rule more seriously. Conse­quently, the “affirmative” probably would have prevailed, and the building would have been burned. Thus, the rule making building burning unspeakable would have made it more, not less, doable.

However, one cannot defend the right to preach noxious doc­trines, exclusively on the ground that they cannot persuade. Good ideas have not always won out over bad in the marketplace of ideas.[29] However, the entire Constitution, of which the first amend­ment is only a part, is an important fail-safe against implementa­tion of the worst ideas. For example, Klansman Clarence Branden­burg’s belief that “the nigger should be returned to Africa [and] the Jew returned to Israel”[30] could not be implemented under the equal protection and due process clauses, even if he were able to persuade a majority that he were correct. Of course, there is a the­oretical possibility that he could be so persuasive that we as a country would suspend civil rights and allow mass deportation or genocide. It is a possibility, however, that must be discounted by its improbability. Furthermore, anybody that persuasive would have long since persuaded us to abolish Bickel’s proposed law against advocating genocide.

None of this should suggest that freedom of speech is risk-free. I would hate to count the number of harebrained schemes that have been enacted into law during my lifetime. Many of these schemes were fueled by half-baked passions that reasoned analysis was una­ble to overcome. I also have little doubt that there have been some horrible crimes committed by people who were inspired by bad speeches or worse books. The difficulty is that the only cure for this problem is allowing the government to punish hateful ideas, and surely that cure is worse than the disease. “That at any rate is the theory of our Constitution.”[31]

  1. Entertainment as Speech

It is sometimes suggested that entertainment cannot contribute to the marketplace of ideas, and therefore should not be constitu­tionally protected.[32] Although not all entertainment is speech,[33] that which is speech (such as books, plays, and movies) is entitled to full constitutional protection. The reasons for so holding were developed in a classic, but too often forgotten, Supreme Court opinion, Winters v. New York.[34]

In Winters, New York sought to punish a bookseller for selling magazines containing collections of criminal deeds with pictures and stories “so massed as to become vehicles for inciting violent and depraved crimes against the person.”[35] The State argued that because of the nonideological character of the magazines, they were not constitutionally protected. The Court rejected this argu­ment in a remarkably succinct and perceptive five sentences:

We do not accede to appellee’s suggestion that the constitutional protection for a free press applies only to the exposition of ideas. The line between the informing and the entertaining is too elusive for the protection of that basic right. Everyone is familiar with in­stances of propaganda through fiction. What is one man’s amuse­ment teaches another’s doctrine. Though we can see nothing of any possible value to society in these magazines, they are as much enti­tled to the protection of free speech as the best of literature.[36]

Justice Frankfurter’s dissent from this analysis is worth considering:

Wholly neutral futilities, of course, come under the protection of free speech as fully as do Keats’ poems or Donne’s sermons. But to say that these magazines have “nothing of any possible value to so­ciety” is only half the truth. This merely denies them goodness. It disregards their mischief. As a result of appropriate judicial determi­nation, these magazines were found to come within the prohibition of the law against inciting “violent and depraved crimes against the person,” and the defendant was convicted because he exposed for sale such materials. The essence of the Court’s decision is that it gives publications which have “nothing of any possible value to soci­ety” constitutional protection but denies to the States the power to prevent the grave evils to which, in their rational judgment, such publications give rise.[37]

On the surface, there is much to lend support to Frankfurter’s analysis. If indeed the magazines have no possible value to society, why, given their potential for harm, shouldn’t New York be able to proscribe them? The answer is that the Court did not say that these magazines have “nothing of any possible value to society;” it said: “[WJe can see nothing of any possible value to society in these magazines.”[38] The distinction is crucial. The Court, unlike Frankfurter, was unwilling to limit freedom of speech to its own ability to perceive value. Rather, it imposed an absolute bar on a judge’s power to condition entry into the marketplace on a prelimi­nary showing of merit. Thus, because the line between informing and entertaining is too elusive to draw, even entertainment cannot be kept from the marketplace simply because its value is im­perceptible to the judiciary.[39]

* Copyright retained by author.

** Graham Kenan Professor of Law, University of North Carolina School of Law.; J.D., 1963, Boston University; LL.M., 1964, Harvard. The author would like to thank Mark Mel­rose, Mark Davis, and Mark Anders for their helpful research assistance, and Professors Michael Corrado, Donald Homstein of the University of North Carolina law faculty, and several members of the University of Richmond law faculty for their helpful comments.

[2] See, e.g., Francis Canavan, Freedom of Expression: Purpose as Limit (1984); Alex­ander Meikeljohn, Political Freedom: The Constitutional Powers of the People (1948, 1960); Lillion R. BeVier, The First Amendment and Political Speech; An Inquiry into the Substance and Limits of Principle, 30 Stan L. Rev. 299 (1978); Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 Ind. L.J. 1 (1971); Benjamin S. DuVal, Free Communication of Ideas and the Quest for Truth: Towards a Teleological Approach to First Amendment Adjudication, 41 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 161 (1972).

[3] Two of the most prominent exponents of this theory today are Professors Edwin Baker and Martin Redish. See C. Edwin Baker, Scope of the First Amendment Freedom of Speech, 25 UCLA L. Rev. 964 (1978); Martin H. Redish, The Value of Free Speech, 130 U. Pa. L. Rev. 591 (1982).

Toward A General Theory of the First Amendment (1966); Frederick F. Schauer, Free Speech: A Philosophical Enquiry (1982); Kent Greenawalt, Free Speech Justifications, 89 Colum. L. Rev. 119 (1989); Steven Shiffrin, The First Amendment and Economic Regula­tion: Away from a General Theory of the First Amendment, 78 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1212 (1983).

[5]   See Bork, supra note 1; Canavan, supra note 1.

[6] Professor Baker, supra note 2, is especially vulnerable to this criticism. See, e.g., Fred­erick F. Schauer, Must Speech Be Special?, 78 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1212 (1983).

[7]  See Schauer, supra note 5.

[8]   West Virginia Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 642 (1943).

[9]   Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 339 (1974).

[10]        See, e.g., Abington School Dist. v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 222 (1963) (discussing estab­lishment of religion).

[11]  See, e.g., Lee C. Bollinger, The Tolerant Society: Freedom of Speech and Ex­tremist Speech in America (1986); David A.J. Richards, Toleration and the Constitu­tion (1986); Steven G. Gey, The Apologetics of Suppression: The Regulation of Pornogra­phy as Act and Idea, 86 Mich. L. Rev. 1564 (1988); Suzanne Sherry, An Essay Concerning Toleration, 71 Minn. L. Rev. 963 (1987); Steven D. Smith, Skepticism, Tolerance, and Truth in the Theory of Free Expression, 60 S. Cal. L. Rev. 649 (1987).

[12]  Of the sources listed in supra note 10, Professor Gey is the only exception.

[13] This theme is especially apparent in Dean Bollinger’s writings. See, e.g., Lee C. Bol­linger, The Skokie Legacy: Reflections on an “Easy Case” and Free Speech Theory, 80 Mich. L. Rev. 617, 630 (1982).

[14] Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.S. 516, 545 (1945) (Jackson, J., concurring) (citation omitted).

[15]  See National Socialist Party of America v. Skokie, 434 U.S. 1327 (1977) (Stevens, Circuit Justice 1977) (denying stay); National Socialist Party of America v. Skokie, 432 U.S. 43 (1977) (per curiam); Collin v. Smith, 578 F. 2d 1197 (7th Cir.), stay den., 436 U.S. 953, cert, den., 439 U.S. 916 (1978).

[16]  See Bollinger, supra note 12, at 632-33.

[17]  The hard fact is that sometimes we must make decisions we do not like. We make them because they are right, right in the sense that the law and the Constitution, as we see them, compel the result. . . . [T]he flag is constant in expressing beliefs Americans share, beliefs in law and peace and that freedom which sustains the human spirit. The case here today forces recognition o’f the cost to which those beliefs commit us. It is poignant but fundamental that the’ flag protects those who would hold it in contempt.

Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 420-21 (1989) (Kennedy, J., concurring); see also Arnold H. Loewy, The Flag Burning Case: Freedom of Speech When We Need It Most, 68 N.C. L. Rev. 165 (1989).

[18] See Emerson, supra note 3, at 17; Vincent Blasi, The Pathological Perspective and the First Amendment, 85 Colum. L. Rev. 449 (1985).

[19]  See Frederick Schauer, Slippery Slopes, 99 Harv. L. Rev. 361 (1985).

[20]   250 U.S. 616, 624 (1919).

[21] Id. The philosophical underpinnings of the concept itself probably date back at least as far as John Stuart Mill. See John Stuart Mill. On Liberty (1962).

[22] See Stanley Ingber, The Marketplace of Ideas: A Legitimizing Myth, 1984 Duke L.J. 1 (1984); Baker, supra note 2.

[23]  Of course, there is nothing in the first amendment that precludes government from expanding market access to speakers that otherwise would be unable to participate. For example, a city could build its own “Hyde Park” and permit anybody to speak in it free of charge.

[24]  See Martin H. Redish, Freedom of Expression: A Critical Analysis 46 (1984).

[25]  Alexander M. Bickel, The Morality of Consent, 72 (1975), quoting Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 672 (1925) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Bickel brackets and underscores “[ — the only — ]” to highlight what he deemed to be the unsoundness of the Holmes per­spective. Id.

[26]  Id.

[27]  Id. at 73.

[28]  Id.

[29] See, e.g., Frederick Schauer, Speech and “Speech” — Obscenity and “Obscenity”: An Exercise in the Interpretation of Constitutional Language, 67 Geo. L.J. 899, 915-16 (1979); Harry H. Wellington, On Freedom of Expression, 88 Yale L.J. 1105, 1130-32 (1979); Baker, supra note 2, at 974-81.

[30]  Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444, 447 (1969) (per curiam).

[31]  Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).

[32]   See Bork, supra note 1 at 24-29; Meikeljohn, supra note 1, at 86-87.

[33]  The Court has held motion pictures, (Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.S. 495 (1952)), and dancing, (Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim, 452 U.S. 61 (1981); but cf. Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., Ill S. Ct. 2456 (1991) (holding that nude dancing may not enjoy full First Amendment protection)), to be constitutionally protected speech. Sports like horse racing and prize fighting, which are banned in a number of states, [e.g. Ga. Code Ann. § 10-1-550 (1989) (horse racing); S.C. Code Ann. § 52-7-10 (Law Co-op. 1992) (prize fight­ing)), presumably are not speech. I would guess that the Court would say the same about wrestling, although I do not think I would want to write the opinion explaining why profes­sional wrestling as it is choreographed today is not speech, while dancing is.

[34]   333 U.S. 507 (1948).

[35]  Id. at 513.

[36]  Id. at 510.

[37]  Id. at 528 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting).

37; Id. at 510 (emphasis added).

[39] One could argue that a play, book, or movie should be protected even if we knew to a certainty that it had no ideological value. Cf. Sheldon H. Nahmod, Artistic Expression and Aesthetic Theory: The Beautiful, The Sublime and the First Amendment, 1987 Wis. L. Rev. 221. Because, as Winters tells us, we cannot know to a certainty that any particular play, book, or movie lacks ideological value, we need not resolve this argument. 333 U.S. at 510.